The internet and the social life under capitalism: alienation, fear of abandonment, surplus-enjoyment and "meta-objectification"
In
this article, I will attempt to provide an outline, framework or “long summary”
of my theory of how capitalism morphs our social relations and social life, particularly
through the introduction of the most developed form of long-distance communication:
the internet. I plan on later developing this article into a book, so
think of it as a “book-summary before the book was written”.
I:
LONG-DISTANCE COMMUNICATION AND ALIENATION
When
Karl Marx linked capitalism with alienation, we must not only think of
it as alienation between the worker and their product, but also as capitalism’s
way of alienating workers themselves (or people in general). To understand
this, we must understand the difference between alienation and separation.
To
separate two objects, two people or two ideas means to isolate or segregate
them, removing any means of communication between them. Two nations or two
people that are separated have no means of interacting with one another. Prison
can be thought of as the separation from an inmate to the outer world as long
as we assume that the inmate will not have much access to television or the
internet. Two entities that are separated do not exchange information between
each other in any way.
In a
very “meta” way, the very concept of separation itself separates the concepts
of distance and closeness. Two entities are separated if they are at a very far
“distance” one from another. The closer the two entities get, the less
separated they are. Separation strictly maintains the distinction between “far”
and “close”.
Alienation
is the dialectical reversal of this dichotomy between distance and closeness.
Alienation means to be close at a distance and to be distant when you are
close. Alienation is precisely that concept that blurs the line between this “close/far”
distinction.
Long-distance
communication is one useful product of capitalism’s accelerated technological
progress. The only form of long-distance communication before capitalism was hand-written
communication on paper. When this communication was “private” or “one-to-one”,
it took the form of the letter. When this communication was “public” or “one-to-many”
/ ”many-to-many” it took the form of the book. This was the only form of
alienation pre-capitalism, the one way to “keep close at a distance”, and it of
course comprised a very simplified and inefficient form of communication
compared to the face-to-face interaction: many details are lost (clothing, body
language, facial expressions, tone of voice, etc.) and it was much more
time-consuming.
Capitalism
very rapidly created more forms of alienating long-distance communication:
first the phone, then the mobile phone, then the internet. The internet itself
progresses at a very rapid speed such as to mimic face-to-face interaction more
and more. The telephone call introduced the dimension of the tone of voice into
long-distance communication. Texting introduced the affective dimension of
face-to-face interaction with the introduction of emoticons/emojis. Pictures
and selfies and other forms of media could be shared between people, and the
more technology progressed, the more efficiently they could be shared. Video
calling was later introduced which mimicked real-life interaction almost
directly. Just as the form of communication became more and more similar to
real-life interaction, so did its accessibility: phone plans are becoming cheaper,
the internet is accessible to way more people. Whereas in the early 2000’s the
internet was stuck to the computer, now we have it in our phones who are in our
pockets so it is way more “mobile” as well.
Long-distance
communication is still progressing because capitalism did not end yet: the next
step, after the internet, is virtual reality, thus having long-distance
communication “mimic” real-life interaction even more.
“One
to many” communication evolved as well – the limiting functions of the book,
that is time-consuming to write and can only communicate words (and sometimes
pictures) evolved into the “social media profile” which conveys more
information. Many-to-many communication evolved as well: a book written by
several authors and read by multiple people is way more limiting than the
functions of an online public forum.
Slowly,
capitalism’s alienating function increased: two people who are very far apart
physically (at other ends of the globe) can suddenly be “close” with the aid of
the internet.
The
reverse is also true. Two people who are right next to each other are suddenly
far more apart. People watch concerts through the screen of their phone. People
next to each other prefer to stay on their phone instead of talking face to
face. An anecdote: at the place where I currently work, it is a hybrid-remote tech
job where, even in the cases where I go at the office, we still communicate
through Microsoft Teams. We never have face-to-face meetings since we also have
to include our colleagues from other countries, and thus, our office is a bunch
of programmers who are sitting next to each other and talking to the person
next to them through a laptop & headphones.
Alienation
is a double-edged sword because just as it connects two entities that are “far
apart”, so does it “distance” two entities that are very close. It is not only “closeness
in distance” but also “distance in closeness”. Hence, there is always a price
to pay.
II:
PRIVACY, INTIMACY, ABANDONMENT AND THE THERAPIST INTERNET FRIEND
Fear
of abandonment is a symptom caused by long-term communication. The way most “mental
disorders” manifest is only through the filter of our economic system, so while
you could make an argument that the same “illness” or “cause” still existed in
previous systems (debatable, but let’s assume it true for the sake of argument),
the way it manifested itself was way differently. The symptom of “fear
of abandonment”, for instance, couldn’t have existed in feudalism since there
was barely any abandonment in the first place, social relations were fixed,
stable and long-term: the fear was the opposite, that you were stuck
with the same spouse/landlord/serf/etc. for life. The presence of so many
options of social relations inside capitalism, through the introduction of
long-distance communication, makes the durability and stability of them way
more fragile. The more capitalism advances, the more fast-paced everything is
and the more our attention spans shorten. The newest popular social media always
involves a shorter attention span than the previous one: we moved from online
forums with long walls of text to Facebook, from Facebook to Instagram, from
Instagram to TikTok. Watching 30 minute Youtube videos turned into 30 second “Vines”
and “TikToks”. Albums and songs are getting shorter. Books are getting shorter.
Social
relations are becoming way more fragile as well. The availability of so many options
for friendship or romantic and sexual relationships through the internet accelerates
the fear that you may be abandoned once your other has found someone who is
better to replace you.
This
is why one necessary condition for the sexual revolution and the liberalization
of sexual relationships was not only the invention of more efficient
contraception (ex: the condom) but also the invention of more efficient
long-distance communication (ex: the internet). The internet allows us to have
access to more potential partners and thus the very quality of “a relationship”
in general is degrading and its average lifespan/duration shortens. Notice the
similarity: both condoms and the internet are two forms of alienation, since
the condom is a way of “touching our genital organs without really
touching”, to keep “distant” when we are actually close.
The
possibility of abandonment introduces a positive element too, however. In
short-distance/real-life communication, we only deal with the dimension of
separation and thus, intimacy and privacy are inversely related and they are a
function of time. The more time you know someone for, and the closer you are to
them, the more you can share “intimate” details about your life to them (personal
problems, childhood trauma, sexual life and concerns, etc.). This is because in
real-life communication, people are tied to the context in which you interact
with them. Hence, the possibility of abandonment is low on both sides: if you
tell something personal to your coworker and it goes wrong, you will be forced
to either continue seeing them every day or quit your job (more likely you will
choose the former). Thus, sharing personal details about your life involves
trust and being comfortable with the person, and hence, the less time you know
someone for, the less details you share.
This is not the case on
the internet – there, the less you know someone for, the more you can share
details about your life. The internet is not tied to context but it is the
creator of virtual, temporary contexts. You can find a stranger on the internet
for the sole purposes of venting about your life to them, now there is no
hesitation because you have nothing to lose, if something goes wrong, you can
just abandon each other. This is how the internet created a third category of
people: other than the stranger who you are forced to interact with (high
hesitance to share intimate details) and the person you are close with who you
are also forced to interact with (medium hesitance to share intimate details);
now you have a third category: stranger who you are not forced to
interact with (low hesitance to share intimate details). On the internet,
psychological distance is reversed: the longer you know someone for, the more
hesitant you are to share intimate details with them, since the stakes are
higher and abandoning them has a higher price after you have already built a
friendship. On the internet, the more someone is a stranger, the more “personal”
you can be with them, paradoxically. The dialectic of the internet (and
alienation in general) is that the closer you are with someone, the less close
you are with someone. Hence, the internet has distorted the very way we view
the concepts of intimacy, privacy and psychological distance, considering how
its alienating function overlaps “close” with “far”.
Before the invention of
the internet was the invention of psychotherapy. We usually joke about how our
internet friends are our therapists, but what if we reverse this and say that
the therapist was the first “internet friend”? What if psychotherapy itself was
a precursor to online relationships? After all, this was Jacques Lacan’s point
when he said that the therapist should position themselves as what he called
the “objet petit a”, that object that you only want because you can’t
obtain it, and once you do obtain it, you throw it away as if it was trash. You
are close to your therapist only insofar as you are “far”. In therapy, you
share personal information because they are a stranger, not “in spite of”
– in case something goes wrong, you can just leave them and never see them
again because you won’t interact with them or any of their acquaintances in any
other context.
The internet is the creator
of “empty contexts”, contexts with form deprived of content – virtual spaces
with a specific, designated purpose that can be easily abandoned once that
designated purpose goes obsolete. Psychotherapy was one of the first such empty
contexts, you are interacting with a stranger that you’ve never met for a
specific purpose and that you will never meet again outside of this context.
Hence, the therapist and their patient are not “close” nor “distant”
psychologically, but alienated.
III:
ESSENCE VS. SURPLUS-ENJOYMENT IN SOCIAL RELATIONSHIPS
Here
I am going to use “essence” in the Aristotelian sense where it also designates purpose
as well as definition. For Aristotle, the essence of an object is that
thing without which it wouldn’t be that object anymore. Any social context as
well as any social interaction has an “essence”, a thing that it has or promises
to create, without which you would abandon that social space. Other than the
essence, there are also a lot of other “secondary gains” of socializing under
that environment, which correspond to what Lacan and Zizek may call “surplus-enjoyment”.
They are secondary for two reasons: on one hand, if they were gone, you would
still socialize in that context. On the other hand, even if they remained, you would
still abandon the context as long as the essence is gone.
For
example, you go to work in order to work and receive a salary. Banter with your
coworkers is only secondary, it is a “surplus-enjoyment”. If you stopped
receiving your salary, you’d stop going to work, despite the fact that there
would still be some secondary gains here and there. The essence of a social
context is what we think of as its purpose.
This
is important to keep in mind in order to understand the effects of
technological alienation upon our romantic relationships. There's an infinite
number of ways to classify the way that romantic relationships start, but one
possible "dichotomy", let's say, is whether love was an essence
of the encounter or a surplus-enjoyment. To say that the potentiality of
love is the essence of two people means that a person would stop talking
to you if the potential for you to become their romantic partner would drop to
zero. In other words, I can talk to a girl only for the sake of trying to make
her my girlfriend, but once I realize that the probability of this tends to
zero, I will cut contact with her. I argue that this was the exception
before the internet - it was very hard to do this because people met by a
shared context, they were not able to intentionally alienate themselves: you
met your partner though a common circle of friends, at work, at school, through
a shared interest, so even if they rejected you or something, you were still indirectly
forced to have some contact/interaction with them. In those situations, I say
that love is a "surplus-enjoyment": you have other reasons to chat up
the other person other than the potential for love, and if love happens, it is
a surplus, an "extra", a "bonus".
Then
came the rise of Facebook and other types of social media (Instagram, etc.)
which made this "love as an essence" become easier: people put
profile pictures, you could chat someone up just for that purpose and stop
talking to them once you realize they are not interested in you, it is not
worth it, etc. since you did not have any other things that tied you together.
After social media, even later, came the rise of dating apps like Tinder who
were designed to create addiction and short-term gratification: so now it's
like Facebook but on steroids – on dating apps, we interact just for the sole
purposes of creating a romantic relationship, and once the chances drop to
zero, we abandon each other, and we cannot even pretend that we do not do this,
like it was the case for Facebook and so on.
Of
course, even before long-distance communication, it was still possible to have
social relationships just for the sole purpose of initiating a romantic
relationship (pick-up artists, etc.), but it was way rarer, because you met
most people through a shared context in which the essence was a different one.
Now the balance is starting to shift and it’s becoming more the rule than the
exception. I'm reminded a bit here as well of what Viktor Frankl had to say on
the subject, the man who invented existential therapy: "It is the very
pursuit of happiness that thwarts happiness." - he used to say, in
regards to happiness and success, that you cannot gain it if you intentionally
look for it, but you must have some sort of higher meaning or
"purpose" and then let success and happiness come as a side-effect (as
Zizek’s “surplus-enjoyment”). I wonder how much of this applies to love as
well, whether you only find it when you do not look for it specifically.
This dialectical
reversal of essence and surplus-enjoyment is not only inherent to social
relationships, it happens in most products that are sold on the capitalist “free”
market and it is a process that Slavoj Zizek calls taking the substance out of
substance. Examples: beer without alcohol, coffee without caffeine, soda
without sugar, expensive watches that you can’t read the time from, smartphones
that you can’t call from (“tablets”), etc. In each of these products, the essence
and the surplus-enjoyment are reversed and what was formerly “the purpose”
disappears and what was formerly “extra/bonus” is now “the new purpose”. If
love is a commodity to be bought and sold under capitalism then we would expect
it to behave like all these other products.
IV:
OBJECTIFICATION AND OBJECT-ORIENTED PROGRAMMING
To
return back to my previous point, notice how the meaning of objectification
changes under capitalism. To objectify someone involves the potential for abandonment.
The “classic” form of objectification that has existed in previous economic
systems as well is when you treat someone like what psychoanalysis calls a “part-object”
– something that they possess (ex: a body part, clothing, wealth,
propriety, etc.). To say statements like “I’m in a relationship with you just
because of your money” or “I’m in a relationship with you just because you are
fit” implies their negation: “If you lost your wealth, I would break up with
you” or “If you gained weight, I would break up with you”. Hence, the close tie
between objectification and (potential) abandonment.
This
sort of objectification is slowly getting replaced by a newer form, one that I
may nickname meta-objectification, for a lack of a better word. Here,
the person is not valued for a part-object that they possess, but for the potential
of obtaining or generating a certain part-object: thus, they are abandoned not
when they lose something current that they have, but once they lose the potential
for obtaining it.
Hence,
let us return to the statement in the previous section: “I am talking to someone
only for the purposes of initiating a romantic relationship, and once this
probability drops to zero (ex: they find someone else), I will cut off all
contact”. This is exactly what I mean by meta-objectification – the person
is abandoned not once they lose something they currently have, but once they lose
the potential of having or becoming something.
It
should be clear how this is an invention of capitalism – isn’t this the precise
way in which the employer objectifies their worker? To say “I employed you
only because you are able to produce surplus-value, and once you stop
being able to work, you will be fired” is not to “classically” objectify
them, but to meta-objectify them. To value someone only for their labor
means not to value someone for something they currently have, but for the ability
to produce or obtain something they could have. Better yet, it would be said
that meta-objectification is not to value someone for something that they own,
but for the potential to produce something that they will not own. The
capitalist values the worker insofar that the worker can produce something that
they could theoretically own but that they will deliberately not own, because
it will be given to the employer.
This
relationship between employer and worker is the primordial relationship upon
which all other relationships are based upon inside capitalism: to say that “I
talk to you only for the chance that you might become my boyfriend/girlfriend
and I wouldn’t have talked to you otherwise” means not to talk to someone
for something that they own, nor for something they could potentially own, but for
something they could potentially not-own, for the potentiality of “non-being”,
for the potential that they could conform to my inner fantasy and ideal of what
a “boyfriend” or “girlfriend” should be and behave like.
In a sort-of
ironical way, the tool upon which alienation is based (the internet,
technology, etc.) is based on computer code, and exactly in computer code we find
the same principles of alienation inside capitalism. What a coincidence!
I
will try to explain object-oriented programming in a simple way for the
non-programmer. Object-oriented programming is a paradigm inside programming (a
“way” to organize your code) based upon the concepts of classes and objects.
Classes are abstract descriptions or “recipes” of what a certain piece of data
should contain while objects are the actual instances of that class. For
example I can have a class “car” which generally and abstractly
describes what a car is/has (the class variables – car
name, date of purchase, brand, model, engine power, price, etc.) as well as
what a car does (the class methods: StartEngine(), StopEngine(),
ChangeSpeed(), Accelerate(), SteerLeft(), SteerRight(), etc.). Then I can have
multiple instances or objects of the car class:
various, individual cars that are developed upon that general model.
This
provides a good analogy on the two forms of objectification. “Classical”
objectification based upon part-objects means to treat someone like a
programming object (an actual, individual, present “thing” someone has – for instance:
an individual, actual car that exists). This “meta-objectification” inherent to
capitalism is to treat someone like a programming class (an abstract set
of rules describing how an object should look like and how it should be created
in the first place): in other words, to meta-objectify someone means to value
someone for the potential to turn into an object. The “car” class has
the potential to create multiple objects of the ”car” type (multiple individual
cars). The “worker” class has the potential to create multiple objects of type “surplus-value”,
and so on…
The
slang that characterizes common concerns and anxieties in our relationships
changed to accommodate this new form of “meta-objectification” created by the
internet’s alienation. In the “classic” form of simple objectification, we try
to stay clear of “gold diggers” or “men who only want one thing and it’s
fucking disgusting”. In our era of technological alienation and
meta-objectification, we are worried about “the friendzone”, or the opposite:
people who pretend to be your friend only to get romantically/sexually involved
later. The concern inside the era of meta-objectification is not concern about the
content of a “class” (someone’s wealth, someone’s body parts like breasts
and ass, other possessions), but the very abstract description of that “programming
class”: the confusion stems from the tangling up of the very signifiers that
we use to describe our relationships. People fight about how to define marriage
in order to include or exclude sexual minorities, about how we should define a relationship
in order to include or exclude polyamory and open relationships, they worry
about the friend-zone, and so on. The anxieties reside at the “meta”
level, the level of the signifiers that we use to label our relations in the
first place (spouse, lover, friend, friend with benefits, “one-night stand”,
etc.) – since, as I previously explained, alienation blurs the line
between “people who you are close with” and “stranger who you are distant with”,
so does it imply blurring the distinction between all relationship-signifiers (“labels”).
It’s
the same case when “sex” does not refer to “intercourse” but “man and woman”. Feminism
inside early capitalism, dominated by simple/classic objectification, was concerned
with the rights of individual women, about “individual objects of the woman
class”, so to speak, to continue the analogy with programming. In late-stage
capitalism, we worry not about individual, specific women, but the very
definition of the word “woman” itself – so it is like a programmer who is
changing the very definition of the classes themselves, not with the particular
instances/objects of the class.
V:
ECHO CHAMBERS AND THE “FREE-FLOATING” CONTEXT OF INTERNET SPACES
Just
like the essence/surplus distinction becomes either blurred or dialectically reversed
when it comes to love-relationships, so it does in regards to political debate and
discourse. The introduction of virtual spaces that people use for the sole
purpose (“essence”) of finding a relationship (dating apps like Tinder)
coincided with the introduction of virtual spaces that people use for the sole
purpose (“essence”) of debating politics and other social issues. Just
like it is becoming less common for people to treat love as a surplus-enjoyment
(you interact with someone in a shared context for another reason – at work,
school, etc. and if you fall in love it is a ”bonus” but not the main purpose
of interaction), it is also way less common for people to treat debate
as a surplus-enjoyment (you interact with someone in a shared context for
another reason and if the conversation tends towards politics, you debate that
too, even if that wasn’t the main purpose).
The
internet’s alienation has created “safe spaces” that are ideal for
people with thin-skin who need protection from various forms of (physical or emotional)
danger. Dating apps are a “safe space” for people, and especially women, in the
sense that:
1. The
treat of physical violence is lower to non-existent
2. You
open and close the app whenever you want, so you can never be taken by surprise
and you are always psychologically prepared for the interaction
3. There
is an increased ability to end the conversation abruptly, if you don’t like the
person, without paying the price of the awkwardness in looking impolite if you
were to do that in real-life
4. Social
anxiety and shyness is way lower since everyone is there for the same purpose,
so it takes way less “balls” or “courage” to do it – there is way less uncertainty
about people’s motives and you do not have to initiate a conversation in a
separate context and have the job of changing the context/”mood” itself on your
shoulders anymore (in other words, the dating app does “the first move” for
you)
So
are echo-chambers similar “safe spaces” for political debate. You intentionally
look for virtual spaces with people with the same political opinions as you,
and the algorithm also recommends you videos and posts of things you already
liked and watch, feeding into an infinite positive feedback loop. If dating
apps protect you from “emotional damage” by reducing the anxiety in initiating
a conversation as well as by reducing the pain in rejection (especially in the
one doing the rejection), then echo chambers protect you from “emotional damage”
by reducing the people who disagree with you or who hold other views that might
“offend” you.
As
you can see, just like psychotherapy was one of the first “offline” empty
contexts, so is the internet now full of virtual empty contexts, of virtual
spaces that have specific, designated purposes – purposes that were almost
exclusively a “surplus” in offline communication. Activities that produced
enjoyment only in contexts where they weren’t the “main purpose” of being there
(political banter in the break at work or school, dating and flirting in a
context where you were there for something else, etc.) now produce “non-surplus”
enjoyment (to use a play of words on Zizek’s recent book title) by being the
essence of an empty virtual context created just for that purpose. Remember
that the concept of “purpose” is inherently tied to the concept of “abandonment”,
in the sense that if a social interaction loses its purpose/essence, you
abandon it – a question for further research is: how does this alienating
feature of capitalism and the internet modify the way in which fear of
abandonment manifests in people diagnosed with various “disorders” (borderline
personality disorder, etc.)?
With
echo chambers, again, we are not dealing with a separation of political views,
but with an alienation. People who only spend time in echo chambers are not
separated from people with other political views, they are alienated, because
they still view the opinions of other political camps, just only through the “filter”
of their political ideology. Leftist forums still post news and articles about
popular right-wing takes and vice-versa, just biased articles that were already
reviewed by a leftist/right-wing writer, respectively. With echo chambers, you
are constantly exposed to the opinions of other people, but only after they
were filtered with the confines of your own ideological biases, hence why we
still speak of alienation and not separation. To make a visual analogy: you can
imagine various echo chambers as different rooms in the same house that are
separated by windows, and you can only view your political “opponents” through
these windows – only that these are windows that distort the way in
which you view what is behind them (they bend and shape the image behind the
window).
“Digital
communication redirects information flows in a way that undermines the democratic
process. Information is distributed without passing through public spaces. It
is produced in private spaces and is sent to private spaces. The internet is
therefore not a public sphere. Social media intensifies this communication
without community. Influencers and followers do not add up to a political
public sphere. Digital communities are commodified forms of community. In
reality they are commodities. They are incapable of acting politically.
(…)
On
a meta-level, our crisis of communicative action can be explained by the fact
that the other is disappearing. The disappearance of the other means the end of
discourse. It robs opinions of their communicative rationality. The expulsion
of the other strengthens the autopropagandistic compulsion to indoctrinate
oneself with one’s own ideas. This self-indoctrination produces
self-referential info bubbles, which impede communicative action. With the
development of the auto-propagandistic compulsion, discursive spaces are
increasingly replaced by echo chambers in which the only voice one hears is
one’s own. Discourse presupposes that I can distinguish between my opinion and
my identity. People who do not have this discursive ability hold fast to their
opinions because they feel that their identities are threatened. Any attempt to
persuade them to adopt a different opinion is therefore doomed to fail. They do
not follow the other; they do not listen. Discourse, however, is a practice of
listening. The crisis of democracy is first and foremost a crisis of listening.”
(Byung-Chul
Han, “Infocracy – Digitalization and the crisis of democracy”, Chapter 3: The
end of communicative action)
The “freedom”
to choose your own “suited” virtual space is a false freedom when you realize
that the algorithms that are controlling those virtual spaces are tools of the
private entity that is owning them, and thus, conform only to the rules of capital.
The algorithm (regardless of whether it’s the algorithm of Reddit or of Tinder)
will not give you what is best for you, it will give you whatever sells.
There are no moral or ethical laws here, the only law is the law of supply and
demand. If the dating app can get you addicted through variable-schedule reinforcement
(the same psychological mechanism behind gambling addiction) then it will make
more profit. If the Reddit or Youtube algorithm can get you “addicted to your
own suffering” by giving opinions that offend you in a particular way, but not
too much, it will do that. Whatever will get them most clicks.
Hence
why I bring this up again: the oppressive formula of late-stage capitalism is
not “You will do whatever I say regardless of how you feel” (like it was the
case in feudalism and maybe early capitalism), but “You will do what I say
out of your own free will”. In capitalism, we are encouraged to “be
ourselves”, to “follow our dreams”, and so on, in other words, to do whatever
we want. The next step is for capital to change our desires (through
marketing, advertisement, etc.) in order to give us a false sense of freedom.
Capital is like a dictator that say “You can do whatever you want as long as I
am the one controlling what you want”. Virtual “safe spaces” like dating apps
and echo chambers are oppressive precisely because they give us what we
want, because they activate that short-term gratification and tickle our short
attention spans with a tiny hint of dopamine, leaving us addicted in the end.
The privatization of all political discourse is a threat to democracy and freedom of speech as well. The idea that a few major corporations control major social media sites like Facebook, Reddit and Twitter implies that a few major corporations have control over the narrative and over the results of the next election. The argument “if you don’t like Twitter, you are always free to leave” does not work because social media has become such a large component of our lives that banning someone off of all social media is equivalent to banning someone from Town Square and telling them “If you don’t like the new rules of Town Square, you are always free to create your own Town Square”. The politically correct liberal-left argument that if you don't like a social platform that censors you, then you are always free to leave ("because it's a private corporation and it can do whatever it wants") is like the capitalist-employer right-wing argument that "If you don't like how your employer treats you, you are always free to quit your job and look for work somewhere else (and starve in the process)" - it does not take into account externalities such as the network effect or, more simply, that you are indirectly forced through the lack of alternatives.
VI:
CONCLUDING THOUGHTS
There
is much more to say, including the role that priests and the church played
between feudalism and capitalism, the priest as the precursor to the
psychotherapist (“the first stranger you are close with”), the relationship
between big data and the ruling ideological narrative, the relationship between
the principles of capitalism and the four principles of object-oriented
programming (encapsulation, inheritance, abstraction, polymorphism), the
difference between smooth and striated spaces in Deleuze’s philosophy, the “be
yourself” culture of faux authenticity, the online internet persona vs. the
real-life persona, the commodification of love and the relationship between
dating apps and the Lacanian “big Other”, etc. The article is getting long so I
will leave the rest for the book (if I ever write it). I will end this with
another quote by Byung-Chul Han:
“The
influencers on YouTube and Instagram have internalized the neoliberal
technologies of power. Whether they peddle travel, beauty or fitness, they
constantly invoke freedom, creativity and authenticity. Their advertisements
are not seen as annoying because the products are cleverly embedded in the
influencers’ self-presentation. Whereas people use ad-blockers to remove
conventional advertisements on YouTube, they intentionally seek out the
influencers’ ads. Influencers are worshipped as idols, and this gives their
presentations a religious character. Influencers claiming to be motivational
coaches present themselves as saviours, and their followers, their disciples,
take part in the influencers’ lives by buying the products the influencers
pretend to consume in staged scenes from their everyday life – a kind of
digital Eucharist. Social media is a church: like is ‘amen’; sharing is
communion; consumption is salvation. The repetition that influencers use as a
dramatic tool does not bore; rather, it gives the whole affair the character of
a liturgy. At the same time, influencers present consumer products as means of
self-realization. We consume ourselves to death while realizing ourselves to
death. Consumption and identity become one. Identity itself becomes a
commodity.
We
imagine that we are free, but in reality our entire lives are recorded so that
our behaviour might be psychopolitically controlled. Under the neoliberal
information regime, mechanisms of power function not because people are aware
of the fact of constant surveillance but because they perceive themselves to be
free. Whereas Big Brother’s telescreen is untouchable, the smart touchscreen
makes everything available and consumable. It thereby produces the illusion of
a ‘freedom we have at our fingertips’. Under the information regime, being free
does not mean being able to act but being able to click, like and post. For
this reason, there is little resistance to the regime. It need not fear
revolution. Fingers, by themselves, are not capable of genuine action. They are
only an organ for making consumer choices. Consumption and revolution exclude
each other.”
(ibid.,
Chapter 1: The Information Regime)
Comments
Post a Comment