Love, the desire to be desired and the Master-Slave dialectic
What follows is an excerpt from my upcoming book, "Intersubjectivity and its paradigms". It contains my own interpretation of Hegel's master-slave dialectic as viewed through Lacanian psychoanalysis. Note that when I say "psychotic", in this post, I am not necessarily referring to schizophrenia and other psychotic disorders, but to the psychotic clinical structure.
“THE ONE WHO FIRST
GIVES IN”
In “The Phenomenology
Of Spirit”, Hegel introduces his idea of the master-slave dialectic (also often
translated as the “master-servant” or “lord-bondsman” dialectic) in order to
explain the sublation of consciousness into self-consciousness. It is described
by a myth: two people that meet and start fighting each other to the
death in order to be the only person alive, since the existence of another
consciousness threatens one’s monopoly over self-consciousness itself.
Eventually, one of the two people cares for their life more than the other and
begs to stop the fight. That person who “gives in first” becomes the
slave for the other one, who becomes the master – the master is the one who was
willing to risk their life more, and by caring less about death, they were able
to fight for more. The one who cares about their life more becomes the slave
because the one who is willing to risk their life more will put certain
conditions over the other in order to stop the fight.
More concretely, you
can imagine this: A and B have a physical fight, and after many cuts and
bruises, after both of them start realizing that if they continue fighting for
more, they’ll eventually die, there will be one who cares about living a bit
more than the other, let’s say that B cares about their life more than A. Then
B will propose to stop the fight: “Hey, A, let’s stop fighting because if we
continue, one of us will die and I don’t want it to be me”. A was willing
to continue fighting for more time than B (for how much, we cannot know
exactly), so A now has two choices: a). ignore B and continue fighting, or b).
agree to end the fight under certain conditions. A would be an idiot to not put
certain conditions on ending the fight, since A is willing to risk their life
more than B, A now has more “leverage” to negotiate the terms of their future
relationship (“I will stop punching you if you agree to do this favor for me”).
The more someone is willing to risk their life, the more leverage they have to negotiate
a contract of subservience over the other.
The general formula is
this: the one who “gives in” first becomes the slave for the other one, who
becomes the master.
It is the same thing
in capitalism, where the employer almost always has more leverage to
negotiate the contract with their new employee, after a successful job
interview, and thus, have a certain kind of power over them – it is just like
Hegel said, because the employee needs the employer more than the employer
needs the employee, and thus, the employer fears the death of their
relationship less!
As you can see, this
myth can be interpreted literally or metaphorically (in the case of the
employer-employee relationship, the death was a metaphorical death of the
relationship itself). Metaphorically speaking, it is a good allegory for what
goes on in every relationship of ours. The master-slave dialectic is the
resolution for the dialectical tension between how we want others to be and how
they themselves want to be. It is the dialectical reversal over the problem of
the persona: the persona is a negotiation between how others want us to be and
how we ourselves want to behave (the “being yourself vs. being loved” dilemma)
– and it corresponds to the fantasy of the neurotic (algebraically represented
by Lacan as “$ ◊ a”). The master-slave dialectic, on the other hand, is
the fantasy of the pervert (algebraically represented by Lacan as „a ◊ $”), it is the compromise between „letting the
other be themselves” vs. „loving them”. In other words, if you do not tell
other people what to do or how you want them to be like, they will behave in a
particular way that offends or upsets you. If you do try to control or change
other people, you risk changing them so much that you are only „talking to
yourself in the mirror through others”, like the psychotic does. Or,
like I explain in my previous book:
“We all wish for better social skills. Even
those with very good social skills wouldn’t mind even more charisma, even more
persuasion power, even more social awareness, and so on. But how do unlimited social
skills look like?
Imagine your social skills become so good that
you can charm or persuade anyone into doing anything you want. You become so
good at applied psychology that you even have the superpower-like ability to
control the tone of the people’s voices and their exact choice of words and
speed of talking. You can make anyone, with enough effort, do anything to
anyone else.
In this hypothetical reality, once you become
so powerful, how much of the other is “human” anymore? If any one person can be
controlled into doing anything, regardless of initial resistance, can we call
them ‘human’ anymore? This is how a robot behaves, be it programmed by
classical programming or by artificial intelligence. You will soon realize how
extremely lonely you are. Each person is a puppet of your decisions, and is
thus controlled by you, it is as if no other person would exist, since you
would only interact with yourself. To be unlimitedly persuasive is like playing
a game of chess with yourself: you make both moves.
Thus, the desire for social interaction is the
secret desire for failure. The analogy with the chess game is so good because
it is also an example: we play two-player games usually when there is at least
a small chance for failure, either with other real-life people (in person or
over the internet) or with bots. This is the masochistic nature of humans: we
do not want it to get easy.”
(Ștefan “Lastrevio” Boros, “Love, politics,
social norms and sex”, Chapter XIII: ANXIETY, SHYNESS AND WHAT MAKES US HUMAN)
If everyone would do
as you wish, they would have no free will and no subjectivity, everyone else
would just be a clone of yourself (like in the psychotic’s fantasy). The
master-slave dialectic is, thus, this dialectic between “making people do what
you want” and “letting people do whatever they want”. You choose the former,
and you regress into psychosis, since everyone else is just a clone of
yourself. You choose the latter, and you are in conflict with everyone, since
no on behaves as you wish.
This is what Hegel
meant when he explained that the existence of another consciousness threatens
our own monopoly over self-consciousness itself. The psychotic fantasy is an
attempt at such a monopoly, an attempt to make everyone else “a clone of you”, or
like I previously explained in this book when describing the paradigm of
meaninglessness, “to talk to yourself through others”. Perversion,
instead, is an attempt at a resolution to this master-slave dialectic, at
“controlling others without controlling others”, or at “making other people do
what you want out of their own free will”.
This is how we can
interpret Lacan’s name for the last lecture in his eleventh seminar: I
love you, but, because inexplicably I love in you something more than you—the
objet petit a—I mutilate you. We all want attention (what Hegel
would’ve called “recognition” of our existence), but we want a
particular kind of attention, we want others to love us in the way we want to
be loved or “recognized”, in a way that conforms to our fundamental fantasy.
Yet, in this process of controlling the way in which others love us, we risk
“mutilating” them, as Lacan says, in changing the other person so much that
they are not “another subject” anymore, but a mere clone or reflection of
ourselves. When we have “psychologically mutilated” the other so much that they
do not have any freedom to choose the way in which they love us, they are no
longer a different subject, but we are just talking to ourselves through the
other, we have created a clone of ourselves (as Hegel would’ve said: we have
achieved monopoly over self-consciousness).
Moving on, what
happens when one of the two people gives in first and becomes a slave? In real
life, we are dealing way less often with physical fights to the death, but we
are dealing with potential “metaphorical deaths” of certain relationships. Hence,
the formula for my own interpretation of the master-slave dialectic in our
day-to-day lives is this:
1. Replace “physical violence” with the violence
of absence or silence itself, the violence inherent in ignoring each other or
in not saying/doing anything
2. Replace “death” with the metaphorical death of
a conversation or of a relationship
This is the most
common scenario: two people stop talking to each other and each person waits
for the other person to text/message them first, or to make the first move.
You see this a lot in dating and relationships, but you also see this after two
friends or family members have an argument and each wait for the other person
to apologize first, or to at least attempt to make-up first. It is often
justified that “you do not want to look desperate”, but I think this is more
often a cope, a retroactive justification of this behavior. In actuality, we
desire to be desired. Desire is a hole, a gap, a lack in ourselves (“what
we do not have, what we lack, what we miss”). However, to desire love
means to desire the other’s desire, to want to be wanted, this creates a whole
ton of problems since you attempt to fill in your lack with the other person’s
lack (to fill your inner emptiness with the other person’s inner emptiness).
The person who texts first, for example, signals to the other that they need
this relationship more than the other. If we stop talking for a week and
suddenly you message me “Hey, what’s up?”, you just communicated that you
needed to talk more than I needed to talk – in other words, you feared the death
of the relationship more than me.
This desire to be
desired cannot be communicated since it is precisely the point at which speech
intersects impossibility. If people were to actually “say what they
want” in a relationship, a lot of conversations would happen like this: “Hello,
I want you to message first. Oh wait, I just did…”. Hence, the desire itself is
self-defeating, a sort-of “self-censoring desire”.
The psychotic
structure forecloses this gap created by the master-slave dialectic, and the
psychotic answer to the master-slave dialectic is “absurdity” or “nonsense”. I
once invented a joke in order to explain how the master-slave dialectic works
for psychotics:
A schizophrenic boy has a crush on his paranoid
classmate. One day, the schizophrenic boy texts his paranoid classmate: “Hello,
I want you to send the first message”, not realizing that by writing this, they
just sent the first message.
The paranoid girl replies: “Hah, you thought
you can deceive me? I know that you are lying, that you are not actually
wanting to send the first message and actually wanted me to send the second
message! I will not fall prey to your tricks!”, and then hits send, not knowing
that she just sent the second message.
Of course, this
example is exaggerated, but you may see from time-to-time examples from real
psychotics who may say stuff like “Hey, I always am the one inviting you
out, how about this time you do the inviting? Invite me now.”. Such a mode
of intersubjectivity is inherently solipsistic, as I often said in previous
chapters, since it denies the other person any freedom to choose their own
answer, you are just attempting to “turn two into one”, to make the other
person a part of you or a clone of yourself.
Romance novels, movies
and shows are infamous for depicting a utopian, exaggerated or unhealthy vision
of love and are widely criticized for that. However, there is one romance anime
that is probably one of the only ones that depicts a more or less realistic
picture of love: “Kaguya-sama: Love Is War”. It is a romantic comedy
that caricatures the master-slave dialectic: two wealthy Japanese high school
students, coming from high-class families, fall in love with each other and yet
are too proud and narcissistic to confess their love first, as they
believe whoever does so first would "lose" in their relationship. The
story follows their many schemes to make the other one confess or at least show
signs of affection. While, of course, parodying and exaggerating the dialectic,
the main premise of the show is at least realistic – to love someone without
being loved back (or, alternatively, to love/desire someone more than
they love/desire you back) puts them in a position of power over you, which is
one reason why most people have so many defense mechanisms to hold back from
doing so too early (anxiety, shyness, paranoia/skepticism, pride/narcissism, etc.).
If you admit that you are under their spell, but that they are not under your
spell, often times you can, indeed, be more easily manipulated. Love, that is,
the desire to be desired, is the lack in oneself that tries to be filled
in by the lack in the other, and thus, to admit to someone that you love them
is like showing them the place in your body where you have an open wound – now
that they have that information, you may be at their feet, because they know
the place to strike if they happen to want to hurt you.
THE MASTER BECOMES
DEPENDENT ON THEIR SLAVE
What happens in the
resolution of the master-slave dialectic? In the case where “death” means
“metaphorical death of a relationship”, both people remain silent instead of
fighting, waiting for the other person to message/hit them up first. The person
who gives in first demonstrates that they need this relationship more than the
other. The person who is “colder”, the one who replies back harder, can now
become the master: they can (more or less indirectly) put certain terms and
conditions onto the other person regarding when and how they can get a reaction
out of them. For example, they now have the power to reinforce certain
behaviors over others – reply faster when the slave did something you like in
that day, reply slower when the slave behaved improperly in that day.
Hegel continues to
explain how the slave “works” for the master, and the master profits off of the
labor of the slave. As a general formula: the slave does all the work, the
master tells the slave how to do that work. In the case of conversation, the
slave is usually the one directing the conversation (regardless of how
paradoxical this may sound, the slave is the one with control over the
conversation), the one who is constantly thinking of what to say, coming up
with subjects of conversation, of new topics to be discussed, asking questions,
and so on. In this case, the “metaphorical death” in the myth of the dialectic
is not “the death of the relationship” but “the death of the social
interaction/the conversation”, represented by the infamous “awkward
silence”. The slave is the one who fears the awkward silence more (the death of
the conversation), so they will be the first one to try to “make the
conversation work”. In this case, the slave is the one doing more of the
work (or all of the work). In other words, the person who first breaks the
awkward silence becomes the slave – they are doing more of the work while
reaping less of the benefits, but at the same time, the master (the one who
does not break the awkward silence) now depends on the slave! Of course,
this master-slave relation may change every few minutes in an actual social
interaction.
It’s a similar case in
the larger context of a relationship, where the person who fears the death of
the relationship more will usually put more work into making that relationship
work. That person is the slave – the master gains power over the slave by
having indirect control over what exactly the slave is doing with the
relationship, while putting in little-to-none of the work.
The summary of the power-relation
is this: the slave works for the master, and thus the master is dependent on
the slave. In other words, the slave “gives” and the master “takes”. The master
is positioned in the selfish or egoistical position where they do little to
none of the work and receive most, if not all of the benefits. On the other
hand, the slave is “being taken advantage of” – they do most to all of the work
and receive little to none of the benefits of the work. However, this
relationship has a “twist”, because while it may seem at first glance that the
master has all of the power, that it is “better” to be a master in life, that
you’d rather live as a master than a slave, you have to remember that the
master is dependent on their slave(s).
Let us go through two
other simple examples. The first example: a rich person (the master) having
literal servants/slaves for all of their life. They were born rich, and were
always rich, and thus never needed to learn how to cook, how to clean, how to
take care of themselves. For all of their life, other people did work for them:
this rich person always had a multitude of servants who cleaned their house,
who cooked for them, and the rich person never worked a day in their life. We
are fooled to believe at first glance that the rich master has all of the power
and the slaves are being taken advantage of. But there is a specific
‘perverted’ power the servants have: the master relies on the servants for
their bare existence. If the servants all decided to leave one day, organize a
strike or something, or if the rich person suddenly lost all their money, or if
the relationship between the two would break for some reason, the servants
would go on with their lives, the master wouldn’t. The master would be left all
alone with no one to cook for them, clean for them, etc. They also wouldn’t
find a job, since they never thought that they will work a day in their life,
so they will soon die of hunger all alone. In other words, because the master
relied on other people to do all the work, they depended on others, and when
the other is gone, the master is dead. Hegel’s point was that the struggle was
one of life and death, and that the master ‘affords’ being a master because
they do not fear death. In other words, the position of the master is “I
have nothing to lose, so I can afford to risk everything, and potentially win”.
Many of us are faced in life with such situations in which we hit rock bottom
(in our career, in a relationship, etc.), when things get so bad that they
simply can only get better from now on, and in the most paradoxical way, the
very fact that we have nothing gives us something: the very fact that we have
nothing to lose anymore give us a certain form of ‘perverted’ power: the very
loss of all power is a power in of itself.
Let’s take another
example of, probably, the most common master-slave dialectic: the newborn and
the parent. A newborn is always the master of their parents, and the parents
are the slaves/servants of the newborn. A newborn cannot take care of
themselves, and thus inherently depends on their slave (parent) for their bare
survival. The parent is the slave: they do all of the work and reap little to
none of the benefits in this relationship. However, if the relationship between
the two would suddenly break for some reason, the parent can survive on their
own, the child will die. The newborn is the master: they do none of the work,
others work for them. The newborn is the “boss” in the relationship as well
because they order the slave around through their cries (“feed me”, “take care
of me”, etc.).
THE MASTER IS
UNSATISFIED WITH THE SLAVE’S RECOGNITION
According to Alexandre
Kojève’s interpretation of Hegel, the master enslaves the servant, gets the
recognition they sought but are, in the end, unsatisfied. By the way, Kojève is
the one who first came up with the idea that Hegel’s master-slave dialectic is
inherently related to the idea of “the desire to be desired”, and Kojève was
Lacan’s professor, hence why Lacan focused so much on this idea. The master is not
satisfied with the slave’s recognition because recognition (“attention”, “love”,
etc.) is only valuable if it comes from an equal or from someone above.
The paradox is this:
we want attention from others, when they do not give us that kind of attention
that we wanted, we gain power over them, they start giving us the attention but
now we are dissatisfied because we do not know if the attention they give us is
authentic or if they give us that attention just because we have power over
them.
For example: if you
are an authoritarian boss at work who micromanages everyone, your employees
might constantly compliment you, be nice to you, etc. but you are not satisfied
with this attention, because it is very likely that they are doing it just
because you are their boss, and thus do not really mean it. Your
employees are so nice to you because they gain something by being nice to you
and/or they lose something if they are not nice to you.
A second example: many
people who feel themselves at the bottom of “the social hierarchy” envy the
people on top who get all the attention, all the likes, all the women, all the
social media followers, all the fame, etc. They want that power, but if they
manage to obtain it, they are now at the top of the social hierarchy and remain
unsatisfied – now they will complain about the opposite thing: everyone is nice
to me just because they expect something in return, people who rejected me in
the past now want to be my friend just because I’m famous, etc.
The moral lesson of
this is the same as of all Lacanian psychoanalysis: we do not know what we
want, when we obtain what we think we want we often end up unsatisfied, we want
more of it, or now we want to get rid of it because it is not like we imagined,
etc. The grass is always greener on the other side, so be careful what you wish
for. Or, like Beiser put it:
“If the self and other are to one another as
master and slave, then the master still does not get the required recognition
of himself as autonomous and independent. The master degrades the slave to the
status of an animal and reduces him to an instrument for his own ends. The
recognition of the slave is therefore of little value, if not worthless, to
him. It is not the free recognition of another rational being, but it is only
the humbled submission of an animal. Recognition loses all value if it comes
from domination or coercion; it is only of value when it derives from the free
choice and judgment of another. Since the master despises the slave, he does
not get the assurance that he is after.
(…)
If the master is to gain recognition as a free
being, then he has to recognize the slave as a free being. For the master gains
reassurance not from the submissive acknowledgment of an inferior but only from
the recognition of an equal. If the master recognizes the slave as a free
being, then he also ceases to degrade himself to the level of his animal
desires. He proves that he is rational because he recognizes that another
person is an end in itself.
(…)
The
master proves his rationality when he finally recognizes the equal and
independent reality of the slave. If he does this, that shows that he acts
according to universal laws that grant someone else the same rights as himself.
The master proves his freedom not by dominating this slave, then, but by
treating him as his equal. Thus, Hegel proves the wisdom behind Rousseau’s
famous lines: ‘He who believes himself a master of others is more a slave than
they.’
(…)
This experience brings the dialectic to its
conclusion. The self knows that it is rational because another rational being
recognizes its autonomy. But it also knows that it is rational because it
recognizes the autonomy of another rational being. In other words, the self
knows that it is rational only through mutual recognition.
(…)
He finally admits that he is not the only
self-conscious being, but that there is another such being. The self
acknowledges that the other is not simply its own representations because it
sees that the other is outside its conscious control. It cannot consume the other,
as if it were an inanimate object; and it cannot treat it as a means to satisfy
its desires, as if it were a slave. Rather, it admits that the other is outside
its conscious control because it is an end in itself, a being that has a right
to live according to its own self-appointed ends, even if they do not agree
with the self’s own ends. So, for Hegel, to recognize another rational being as
an end in itself is the refutation of nihilism. By such recognition, the
solipsist has to concede that not all reality is within its conscious control,
and that there is another rational being having equal status to itself.”
(Frederick Beiser, “Hegel”, Chapter VIII:
Solipsism and Intersubjectivity)
Take the paragraphs from
Beiser’s book that I just quoted and replace “solipsist” with “psychotic”,
since I already explained previously in the book why all psychotics are unconsciously solipsistic (they behave like how you would expect a
solipsist to behave). Hence, what Kojève and Beiser both missed is that there
is a category of people for which this is less of a problem – the psychotically
structured subject. For the psychotic, the dissatisfaction of being a
master recognized by a slave is minimal, it is still there sometimes, but it is
more of a practical manner. A psychotic person might ask themselves things like
“Are they nice to me just because I am rich and they expect something in
return?” as well, but from a purely practical, pragmatic, cold and “logical”
point of view: they worry that once they lose their money, they might lose the
attention/love they get as well, but as long as they have the money, they do
not care that the attention is “inauthentic”, that they are loved/appreciated
just because of a part-object that they possess (ex: money, social media followers,
influence, etc.). For the psychotic, temporarily taking the position of the
slave can be a means to an end but never an end in of itself. Psychotics desire
to be the master. It is only for the neurotic and perverted subject that always
being a master is an unpleasant experience in of itself.
In every other case however,
the best resolution of the master-slave dialectic is mutual slavery. If both
people are masters (both people want to be the one who “takes” in a relationship,
both people want to be loved unconditionally), then there is no one from who to
take, and it results in a fruitless competition. If both people are slaves
(both people seek to be the one who “gives” in a relationship, both people seek
to love unconditionally), then it is not only a win-win, but an authentic one.
This is the homeostasis
towards which every romance should strive towards: mutual unconditional
love. It is, however, an unrealistic ideal that the lovers can only infinitely
approach but never quite reach, usually, since this balance is often disturbed
by various external interventions in the relationship (logistic manners
regarding work and planning, incompatible schedules, possible competitors,
etc.) – the disturbance of this balance starting the master-slave dialectic
again. The path towards mutual unconditional love (the “slave-slave” dialectic,
so to speak) is a long path and you cannot achieve it by the snap of a finger,
since trust and vulnerability are its preconditions. This homeostasis of mutual
slavery is analogous to giving someone a gun that they can kill you with and
trusting them to never using it. But it is only in such cases where love
reaches its highest, most “pure” form: if the other person has nothing to gain
by loving you and nothing to lose by not loving you, only in those cases we can
speak of an ultimately “pure” love – an ideal one should tend towards but that
is impossible to reach exactly.
This chapter also counts
as a refutation of Jung’s claim that “love and power are opposites”:
“But there is no energy unless there is a
tension of opposites; hence it is necessary to discover the opposite to the
attitude of the conscious mind. It is interesting to see how this compensation
by opposites also plays its part in the historical theories of neurosis: Freud’s
theory espoused Eros, Adler’s the will to power. Logically, the opposite of
love is hate, and of Eros, Phobos (fear); but psychologically it is the will to
power. Where love reigns, there is no will to power; and where the will to
power is paramount, love is lacking. The one is but the shadow of the
other: the man who adopts the standpoint of Eros finds his compensatory
opposite in the will to power, and that of the man who puts the accent on power
is Eros. Seen from the one-sided point of view of the conscious attitude, the
shadow is an inferior component of the personality and is consequently
repressed through intensive resistance. But the repressed content must be made
conscious so as to produce a tension of opposites, without which no forward movement
is possible.”
(Carl Jung, Two Essays on Analytical
Psychology, p. 78)
Jung’s mistake is in
viewing power as a psychic energy in of itself, a form of “libido”, drawing
inspiration from Nietzsche’s and Adler’s concept of the “will to power”, just
like he views Eros and Thanatos as the other two kinds of libido. However,
power is not a psychic energy isolated in a person’s psyche, but, as we know from
Hegel, a social process drawn from our desire to be desired (our desire for
mutual recognition). The relationship between love and power, thus, is much
more complicated, since power is more akin a vector that has a certain
direction. Having power over someone is not the same as submitting to someone’s
power. The will to power and love annihilate each other only insofar as both
partners in an equation take the selfish attitude of the master – but love and
power go hand-in-hand quite well when they approach the ideal of “mutual slavery”.
Power is inherently related to the concept of dependence. If someone depends on
you, you have power over them. The end-goal of love is codependence. In
a relationship of codependence, both partners have power over each other. So,
we cannot speak of love and power as two sides of the same coin.
In our highly
individualistic modern capitalist society, dependence is becoming more and more
pathologized, not only in psychology, but in society in general. Both men and
women are bombarded everyday with worshipped ideals of independence –
men are given “Red Pill” masculine relationship advice about how to not submit
to a woman and how to hold power in a relationship, women are given the feminist
ideal of the “independent” woman who does not need men. The result of independence
is the death of love, there is no love without codependence. Codependence
does not kill power however, it just “inverts” it, so to speak. In a romantic
relationship of codependence, power is still there, it’s just that it functions
in a more proper way than in the non-relationship of “mutual independence” or
in the competition of the “master-master” deadlock.
Wonderful synopsis of the twisting of power dynamics in loving relationships.
ReplyDelete