Why Psychoanalysis is not (Pseudo)scientific, but Philosophical | The Revolutionary Potential of Psychoanalysis in the Artificial Intelligence age

 

I: THERE ARE THREE POSSIBLE MEANINGS OF A “SCIENTIFIC” THERAPY

 

            Much has been said about the scientific status or ‘validity’ of various psychotherapeutic approaches, especially of the oldest one: psychoanalysis[1],[2],[3],[4],[5]. The commonly-held, mainstream view is that psychoanalysis is an outdated, pseudoscientific or unfalsifiable practice based on excessive speculation without enough grounding in empirical, everyday experience or in strictly verifiable (and/or falsifiable) claims about reality. This is usually contrasted with the (in)famous Cognitive-Behavioral Therapy (CBT) as well as its related cousins (DBT, ACT, MCT, MCBT, REBT, etc.) which is considered the most scientific “evidence-based practice”. The third type of psychotherapies, humanist therapies (existential, Gestalt, person-centered therapy, etc.) are either viewed as somewhere ‘in-between’ psychoanalysis and CBT, or simply ignored in this debate.

            What is most wrong in this debate is not the answers that are given to the questions, but the very way this debate is held. The question of whether a therapy is “scientific” or not is a bad question because it is not clear enough in the first place. Let’s split it up into multiple categories - generally speaking, there are at least three different ways in which a therapy can be scientific or not:

1.     In the results of the practice. Various psychometrics can be used in a double-blind controlled study in order to test the effectiveness of the therapeutic practice itself on a sample of patients. A meta-analysis, then, can gather the results of multiple such studies, measuring the effectiveness of a therapy in reducing various symptoms (over a period of time) of mood disorders, anxiety disorders, psychotic spectrum disorders and many more. In this particular case, the theory behind the therapy has no relevance, we are simply empirically testing whether applying it in practice “works” in reducing symptoms or not, we are not yet testing why it works. In this way of defining the scientific status of a therapy, almost all mainstream therapies are pretty much on equal ground in treating mood and anxiety disorders. Psychoanalysis in particular is just as effective as CBT5, so if all you care about is that a therapy ‘works’ in reducing symptoms, there is no reason for you to privilege one over the other.

2.     In the theoretical foundation of the practice. CBT is a theory of how thoughts, emotions and behavior influence each other. Psychoanalysis is a much more complicated theory of how the ego, the unconscious and other aspects of our minds similarly influence each other. In this case, both CBT and psychoanalysis are unfalsifiable[6],[7],[8]. The problem that most psychologies suffer in this regard is a reversal of time itself in the scientific process: instead of coming up with a predictive model that starts with a cause and waits to see if the effect will be the one predicted, the theories attempt to retroactively explain an effect by speculating upon its causes. Skinner’s radical behaviorism and most of evolutionary psychology are the two best examples of this, but most of CBT and psychoanalysis apply too. Most of these theories do not even attempt to make predictions about the future, but instead find a human behavior or symptom, speculate upon its causes and find a bunch of concrete examples proving only that it is possible for the cause to be that one, not that it definitely is the one they claim it is. For example, you can prove anything with evolutionary psychology: No matter what human behavior you observe, you can always speculate with clear logical rigor that it is possible for it to have had an evolutionary advantage millions of years ago, but way harder to prove that this is the advantage it had out of all the possible ones. If we live in a society in which people spend a long time getting to know each other before having sex, the evolutionary psychologists will say that it is because millions of years ago, these couples had a higher chance of surviving by forming a more stable bond, but if we lived in an alternate universe in which everyone had sex within the first hour of meeting a person, the evolutionary psychologists in that universe would say that it is because millions of years ago these people who did not wait spread their genes faster. With evo psych, you can prove anything and its opposite. Just like evolutionary psychology, most of CBT and psychoanalysis are also full of vague, abstract and unfalsifiable assumptions about the possible causes of certain symptoms, only being able to prove that it is possible that the cause they identified is the real cause, but also not being able to remove out of the list of possible causes all the other ones speculated by the other therapies.

3.     In the cabinet itself. Whether a therapy is ‘scientific’ in the cabinet itself with each individual patient has nothing to do with whether it had scientific validity in the research lab (1st version of the question) or whether the theory it is founded upon has scientific validity (2nd version of the question). In this 3rd way of viewing the scientific validity of a psychotherapy, we are asking ourselves whether the patient/client themselves is put in the position of a scientist of their own psyche. Only in this 3rd way of defining the scientific status of a therapy, only here is CBT “more scientific” than all the other therapies combined! Indeed, the theory behind CBT is unfounded, but the patient themselves is put in the position of empirically searching for the validity of their own thoughts. In other words, there aren’t good scientific studies proving or disproving the theoretical foundations upon which CBT is built, but the CBT therapist is definitely making the patient do a study on themselves, trying to find, for example, evidence that their thoughts are ’realistic’ or not. Every CBT therapy session is a scientific study where the patient is the little scientist and the object of study is their psyche. That does not automatically logically imply that the theory as a whole is scientific.

To sum up this first part: CBT and psychoanalysis, as well as most other popular therapies, have a lot of scientific research to prove that they can effectively reduce symptoms over a period of time. Here, neither CBT nor psychoanalysis “wins” over the other one. Both CBT and psychoanalysis fail to provide a consistent and empirically valid theoretical foundation upon their therapeutic practice, instead engaging in mental gymnastics where an effect is retroactively searched for its causes. Here, again, neither of the two ‘wins’. Only in the cabinet itself, CBT “wins” over psychoanalysis, because the patient is put in the position of being the scientist of their own psyche. It seems that CBT scored 2/3 while psychoanalysis scored 1/3, does that necessarily make CBT generally a “better” approach than psychoanalysis? No, and this leads us to the next section.

 

II: SCIENCE VS. PHILOSOPHY

 

Where psychoanalysis excels and is 10000 times better than CBT under every metric is its philosophical value. By this, I do not only mean that psychoanalysis is a more useful framework when a philosopher tries to do philosophy. That is only one way in which it excels (ex: film theory, literary analysis, semiotics, the philosophy of symbolism and the interpretation of mythology and pop culture, critical theory and social philosophy, etc.). But beyond this, there is a finer distinction between science and philosophy.

Deleuze and Guattari define philosophy as “the art of forming, inventing, and fabricating concepts”9. One consequence of this is what while science attempts to (truthfully) answer questions, philosophy attempts to tell us that we’re asking the wrong questions, or that the very way we’re framing the questions is part of the problem. Where science settles things, philosophy disturbs them. Where science comes with solutions, philosophy comes with more problems. For Deleuze, a good philosopher is one that knows how to come with the right questions and problems, not one that comes with the right answers and solutions.

Our crisis today is a crisis of the atopic, a crisis that only philosophy can solve, not science. The atopic is the radically different, the wholly Other, the completely foreign, the incomparable. The atopic is whatever is placeless, whatever does not fit under the current system. The atopic does not only stand out, it also stands out from all the ways in which everything else stands out. It’s not only different, it’s also different from all the ways in which everything is different. The atopic is meta-different, it confronts us with difference-in-itself. Any system of categorization has a certain gap or inconsistency that it cannot account for, like the human eyeball’s blind spot, or like Achille’s heel. The atopic is precisely that invisible blind spot, and a confrontation with the atopic forces us to invent an altogether system of how to categorize things just to be able to talk about this new “thing”.

The atopic is not only something new, it’s something that’s so new that it could have not even been imagined up until the encounter with it, making you retroactively reinterpret your entire past just to make sense of this new encounter. The encounter with what is atopic is related to what Jacques Lacan calls a confrontation with the real or what Alain Badiou calls an event. Imagine one day waking up being able to perceive a new color – after this event, you have to rethink the entire way you view colors in general, redesigning the entire color palette just to accommodate for this new one.

For example, an atopic lover is outside the logic of compatibility, they are incomparable. They are not the same as you, nor are they your opposite. Your entire system of how to compare people in the dating market made you think that it can describe everyone, and yet this new person is so strange, so foreign that you have to entirely re-invent your system of how to compare people just to accommodate for this new person. Another example: an atopic politician is not only different from all the other politicians, they are meta-different, they are incomparable. They do not fit into the mainstream left and right wing, but neither are they a moderate or ‘centrist’ compromise, they are so radically new that you have to re-design your entire “political compass” just to accommodate for this new politician.

One can now easily see that only philosophy can confront us with the truly different Other, the atopic. Whereas science applies a pre-existent framework of how reality works in order to accurately make predictions (it solves problems, it answers questions), philosophy tries to make us rethink the very a priori conditions for how we do science in the first place, like that framework about how reality works, for example. A truly groundbreaking philosophical discovery does not attempt to answer our previous questions, but tries to reframe the entire way we ask questions, making us realize that our previous questions did not even make sense.

In other words, the problem with a science without philosophy is that it’s too smart. Nowadays, everything and everyone is smart. We have smartphones, smart TVs and smart fridges. Artificial intelligence is, at its name suggests, intelligent, and as such, it is too perfect. What AI cannot do is philosophy, because the philosopher is not “smart” or “intelligent”, the philosopher works precisely in those imperfections inside science. As such, a philosopher affords being a good idiot. In a course in Spinoza, Deleuze remarked: “To the letter, I'd say they play the fool. Playing the fool, that’s always been one function of philosophy.”10 Byung-Chul Han describes idiotism like this:

 

“Every philosopher who has brought forth a new idiom - a new language, a new way of thinking - has necessarily been an idiot. Only the idiot has access to the wholly Other. The history of philosophy is a history of idiotisms. Socrates knows only that he does not know; he is an idiot. Likewise, Descartes - who casts doubt on everything - is an idiot. ‘Cogito ergo sum’ is idiotic. It takes an inner contraction of thinking to make a new beginning possible. Descartes thinks by thinking Thought.

Today, it seems, the type of the outsider - the idiot, the fool - has all but vanished from society. Thoroughgoing digital networking and communication have massively amplified the compulsion to conform. The idiot does not ‘communicate’. Indeed, he communicates with the In-communicable.”11

 

III: WHY THE ANALYSAND IS A PHILOSOPHER

 

Lacanian psychoanalysts have avoided referring to that person on the couch as either a patient or a client, instead calling them the analysand. Being a patient implies that there is something ‘wrong’ you with that needs fixing and that the psychoanalyst knows better than you, that they are an expert on a problem that you have less knowledge of. But this is not how psychoanalysis works. Being a client implies a business-like contract under the logic of capitalism, it implies buying a service that the therapist sells, and as such, it implies predictability. In other words, a client (of a hairdresser, of an IT company, of a car washing service…) knows what they are getting themselves into. But this is also not how psychoanalysis works, since psychoanalysis confronts the client with the atopic, radically Other. Only a CBT therapist has clients.

The way CBT was intended to be practiced was in a rigidly planned-out business-like way. Judith Beck, the daughter of the inventor of CBT, wrote one of the most popular manuals for Cognitive-Behavioral therapists12. In it, she wrote an entire sub-chapter about “Setting Initial Goals for Treatment and Relating Your Treatment Plan”, a sub-chapter about “Expectations for Treatment”, one about “Devising an Initial Cognitive Conceptualization and Treatment Plan”, one about “Goals and Structure of the Initial Session”, one about “Setting the Agenda” and one about “Problem Identification and Goal Setting”, and the list can continue. In other words, the CBT client is instructed from the very first session that it is favorable for them to have a very specific list of what problems (symptoms) they have, and very specific goals and expectations are set from the very beginning. This is a scientific approach, not in the 2nd sense of the word (the theory is not scientific), but the client himself is instructed to be a little scientist of his psyche. Because the client is put in the position of the scientist, no true radical change can happen. The client is constrained by the plans they initially set out. They are even given homework, most of which is composed of finding “evidence” proving or falsifying their thoughts. Small deviations can be made from the initial plan, how small depending on the therapist themselves, but these are secondary. CBT is a scientific approach geared towards solving problems and answering questions. The theory is not evidence-based, but the client is.

Psychoanalysis works in the opposite ways. The analysand is neither a patient, nor a client, but a philosopher. If the analysand is not a scientist (as psychoanalysis doesn’t force on them a scientific approach towards their mind), that doesn’t automatically make them a pseudoscientist. The psychoanalyst teaches the analysand on how to philosophize, where the object that they philosophize about is their own psyche. While the CBT client is occupied with doing scientific experiments on their own psyche, the analysand is busy philosophizing about their psyche. Because of this, much more radical changes can happen. One huge implication is that in psychoanalysis, you usually do not solve the initial problems you came to treatment for, but seek to find the deeper underlying problems. This can also (more rarely) happen in CBT, but if it does, it’s unintended, a coincidence. But in psychoanalysis, you are taught that the problems that you came to therapy for were not even the real problems to begin with.

CBT hides an implicit utilitarian philosophy geared towards the maximization of happiness. As such, it is extremely ideological. CBT is a product of the material relations of production in society. The compulsion to enjoy is a neoliberal imperative towards productivity. “Hustle culture”, the obsession over achievement and success, and the imperative to be happy as a moral obligation are other examples. “Unlimited Can is the positive modal verb of achievement society. Its plural form—the affirmation, “Yes, we can”—epitomizes achievement society’s positive orientation. Prohibitions, commandments, and the law are replaced by projects, initiatives, and motivation. Disciplinary society is still governed by no. Its negativity produces madmen and criminals. In contrast, achievement society creates depressives and losers.”13.

The discourse of the self-help industry is indicative of the alarming ways we talk about change today. Nowadays, we do not treat ourselves as subjects, but as projects. Everyone wants to “work on themselves”, everyone wants to “invest” in their potential, to “develop” their skills. Personal change itself is viewed as a business-like transaction with goals, plans and expectations set from the very beginning14, just like in CBT. As such, the ‘subject-project’ of the self-help industry or of CBT can never be truly taken by surprise. No atopic change can follow from a business-like contract with your own self. But to be truly free, one must be free from the constraints imposed on oneself. As such, I believe that in order to be free, one must be able to take one’s own self by surprise. Radical, atopic change is truly painful: you are quite literally “shocking” yourself; it is felt like an electric shock.

Psychoanalysis, on the other hand, is geared not only towards the reduction of symptoms like depression and anxiety, but such a radical change in personality and life philosophy that it is often felt like a metaphorical death. The psychoanalyst does not instruct the analysand in the first sessions to set goals and “a treatment plan”, because the change it sets out to make is so radical that the analysand should not even be able to truly understand its full glory in the beginning (else they wouldn’t be truly taken by surprise). Psychoanalysis is a leap of faith, an adventure into the unknown. Because of this, psychoanalysis does not give in to the 21st-century neoliberal ideology of happiness. After analysis ends, the analysand learns how to find meaning in their suffering, not how to optimize their brain into being happy. The meaning of life should not a utilitarian maximization of happiness.

After the death of God, a nihilistic search for happiness, health and comfort is declared as life's meaning by Nietzsche's last man. "‘We invented happiness,’ say the last human beings, and they blink.”15

 

IV: ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE

 

Artificial Intelligence will never replace a psychoanalyst, nor will they replace the analysand. Neither of the two people in the analytic relationship engage in any behavior that may be automatized by Artificial Intelligence. A CBT practitioner, on the other hand, might be partially replaced by AI. In CBT, the client is instructed to think that their symptoms (depression, anxiety, mania, etc.) are caused by certain beliefs that are objectively wrong. The CBT therapist, then, is automatically assumed to be an expert on how to think correctly, and they are paid to train you how to think like them as well. Because of this, they identify logical errors (‘cognitive distortions’) in your thinking. For example, a depressed patient may claim “everyone hates me”, and the CBT therapist will make them write a list of ten situations in life in which they have valid, empirical evidence that another person in their life actually hated them, hoping that the client will fail, realizing that their thoughts were ‘objectively false’ (because of a cognitive distortion called “black and white thinking”). If the client succeeds in writing this list, the therapist might now tell them to do the same with situations in which someone loved them. Their hope is that if their thoughts are corrected to be more realistic or “adapted to reality”, their behaviors and emotion will also follow to be “corrected”.

First off, “adaptation” or “being functional” are conformist categories. Second off, an AI can be trained to identify logical fallacies and cognitive distortions. Both the therapist and the client in the CBT relationship are put in the position of an AI. The client is treated like an AI language model. Their thoughts are treated like a piece of computer code that has a bug somewhere and must be “debugged”. The therapist is also trained to think like an AI language model. Only chatbots do not understand subtext and implications. AI chatbots have an autistic relationship to language, they interpret social situations literally and do not understand contextual cues or the hidden meaning behind people’s words. The CBT therapist is trained to think like an AI language model: when the depressive patient says “Everyone hates me”, they interpret it literally, instead of understanding the possible implications (which change depending on context, ranging from a provocation towards the therapist to do something, to a cry for help or attention, etc.).

Under the regime of AI automatization, every piece of reality that can be copied will be copied, simulated and replaced. Only those people who are truly atopic will remain, because they are unreplaceable, incomparable, they crash the entire system of how to compare people in general where the AI has not been trained on people like them. Those people who are atopic, who are not merely original or unique, but also different from all the ways in which everyone else is different, only those will avoid being replaced by AI.

Slavoj Zizek likes to joke about how capitalism takes the essence out of commodities. We have coffee without caffeine, beer without alcohol, soda without sugar, sugar without calories (artificial sweeteners), smartphones without the possibility of calling (tablets), etc. Now we also have natural selection without nature. Artificial Intelligence is, quite literally, a form of unnatural selection. It’s an artificial selection. Those who fit in with the crowd will be simulated and replaced by AI. Those who stand out from the crowd will also be replaced by AI. Only those who stand out in the very way in which they stand out can crash the system and produce something radically new, atopic. Because of this, both philosophy and psychoanalysis are more relevant than ever before. Psychoanalysis is not outdated. Now it’s more relevant than it ever was, even compared to its inception.

 

 -----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

NOTES AND REFERENCES:

1: Oliver Burkeman, “Therapy wars: the revenge of Freud” (2016);  https://www.theguardian.com/science/2016/jan/07/therapy-wars-revenge-of-freud-cognitive-behavioural-therapy

2: Drew Westen, "The Scientific Legacy of Sigmund Freud: Toward a Psychodynamically Informed Psychological Science" (1998); https://sci-hub.se/https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-2909.124.3.333

3: Mark Solms, The scientific standing of psychoanalysis (2018);  https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC6020924/

4: Erik R. Kandel, “Biology and the Future of Psychoanalysis: A New Intellectual Framework for Psychiatry Revisited” (1999);  https://ajp.psychiatryonline.org/doi/full/10.1176/ajp.156.4.505

5: Jonathan Shedler, “The Efficacy of Psychodynamic Therapy”, (2010);  https://www.apa.org/pubs/journals/releases/amp-65-2-98.pdf

6: https://old.reddit.com/r/Lastrevio/comments/w2bkrd/one_of_the_problems_with_cognitive_therapy_beyond/

7: https://melbournelacanian.wordpress.com/2014/02/03/a-critique-of-cbt-as-ideology-part-1/

8: https://www.amazon.com/CBT-Cognitive-Behavioural-Managerialism-Corruptions/dp/1782206647

9: Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, “What Is Philosophy?”, Chapter 1, p.2

10: Gilles Deleuze, Spinoza cours du 02/12/80, at www2.univparis8.fr, and Philippe Mengue, Faire l’idiot. La politique de Deleuze (Paris: Germina, 2013).

11: Byung-Chul Han, “Psychopolitics: Neoliberalism and the new technologies of power”, p. 82

12: Judith S. Beck - Cognitive Behavior Therapy: Basics and Beyond, 2nd edition (2011)

13: Byung-Chul Han, “The Burnout Society”, p. 9

14: https://lastreviotheory.blogspot.com/2023/06/change-today-why-both-stability-and.html

15: Friedrich Nietzsche, “Thus Spoke Zarathustra”, p. 10


Comments